ANDREW McCARTHY RESPONDS ON PREEMPTION AND ARIZONA

http://www.nationalreview.com/corner/242397/preemption-prosecutorial-discretion-response-heather-mac-donald-andy-mccarthy

Preemption & Prosecutorial Discretion: Response to Heather Mac Donald

Posted on August 03, 2010 3:42 PM

I appreciate Heather’s kind words and her thoughtful response to the points I raised in challenging one argument she made in the course of dismantling Judge Susan Bolton’s ruling on the Arizona immigration law. Heather has good cause to be unsure of how today’s federal courts will resolve the preemption question she posits — in a nutshell: Can a state, consistent with the Constitution, enforce a state-law immigration penalty that is consonant with federal statutory law but contravenes a presidential policy of non-enforcement? My confident assertion that a state can do so is based on my understanding of the Constitution’s division of federal and state power, rather than on how the whimsical federal courts may choose to “evolve” that division.

As Heather suggests, I do draw a bright line between executive enforcement policy (which is politics) and congressional statutes (which are law). On this point, the foundational disagreement I have with Heather is about the Constitution. Heather writes: ”In so exercising his discretion, a president has not entered into some extra-constitutional ‘political’ territory, as Andy seems to suggest; he is operating within his constitutional legal powers.” Respectfully, I think this misinterprets the Constitution, which is foremost a political document, not a legal one.

The Constitution enumerates and divides the political powers of the federal government, reserving to the sovereign states and the people all rights and powers not expressly vested. The fact that the president’s powers stem from the Constitution does not, as Heather infers, mean his exercise of them is a “legal” act; nor does that exercise’s political nature make it “extra-constitutional.”

When, for example, a president commits U.S. armed forces, as the Constitution empowers him to do, in contravention of a statute (e.g., the War Powers Resolution), the federal courts refrain from deciding the dispute because it is a “political question.” Yes, I suppose it can be said that the president is legally the commander-in-chief, and that Congress has followed its legal procedure for passing a law, but the controversy does not therefore become a legal one fit for judicial resolution. It remains a political one to be decided at the ballot box. And, to take another example, one of the main checks given Congress on abuses of executive power is impeachment, which is a political remedy, not a legal one — even though there is a legal process for carrying it out.

The fact that law has no existence absent the discretionary decisions that attend its enforcement does not make those decisions any less political or any more legal. Law defines what we can do; within those parameters, what we choose to do is a political call involving resources and policy priorities. Heather asserts that a law-enforcement decision to refrain from enforcing a law is “as much a part of the law” as the enactment of the law by the legislative process. I don’t agree. After all, try running that in reverse: If there is no statute, law enforcement has no decision to make — if it tries to enforce that which Congress has not enacted, that is a violation of law. Moreover, if the public is unhappy that the cops are pouring out the Colt 45s instead of arresting the loiterers, that can be a major political issue even though there is no legal recourse over the failure to enforce the law. Mayor Rudy Giuliani won reelection going away largely because New Yorkers liked his stepped-up enforcement policy on petty offenses, which reduced overall crime and improved quality of life.

Perhaps because I see the Arizona situation more as a political one than a legal one, I come at it from a different angle. The nation is built on a political power-sharing arrangement in which the states maintained their sovereignty while surrendering certain powers to the national government. Two important things flow from this.

First, the states are sovereign. That is not just a slogan, it is a concept that has real meaning. Inherent in sovereignty is the natural right of self-defense. If states are no longer at liberty to protect their territories and defend their citizens, they are no longer sovereign, and the social compact on which the nation is based is broken.

Second, the presumption in our system is against the forfeiture of rights and powers. The Constitution expressly provides that unless a power has been delegated to the federal government, it is retained by the states. Our law holds that individuals are not deemed to forfeit their fundamental rights unless there has been a waiver that is clear, knowing, and voluntary. I don’t see why sovereign states would rate any less deference. This is critical because (a) the Constitution does not delegate the power of immigration enforcement to the national government (the power to set terms for naturalization, which is federal, is not a power over immigration enforcement), (b) the power to regulate immigration was understood to be retained by the states, as a core part of their police power, for the first century-plus of our nation’s history, and (c) the states have continued to exercise this power and have never forfeited it. In point of fact, until the turn of the 19th century, the pertinent question was whether the national government had any power over immigration enforcement (Jefferson, for example, was quite certain it did not). It was federal power that was dubious; state power was unquestioned. See, e.g., Joseph Baldacchino, “Regulation of Immigration Historically a State Function” (National Humanities Institute, July 19, 2010).

To me, this is the necessary context for any consideration of a federal attempt to prohibit the exercise of state police power within a state’s sovereign territory. Such a prohibition should not happen unless there is a clear constitutional mandate — i.e., an unambiguous indication that the states delegated the power in question to the federal government or that the state’s exercise of the power interferes with some federal right clearly protected by the Constitution. This is what the Supremacy Clause stands for.

Like most judicial inventions, the preemption doctrine, which is the root of my narrow disagreement with Heather, started out harmless enough: holding that where there is a clear delegation of power to the federal government the states either may not act at all (as in the power to coin money or establish a uniform rule of naturalization), or may not act in a manner contradictory to federal law. But here is the problem: judge-made federal law, particularly in constitutional jurisprudence, often becomes nothing more than a gussied up power-grab: either the judiciary usurps the powers of the other federal branches, or the judiciary is the means by which the federal government usurps the power of the states — with the federal courts becoming more powerful because they get the last word. (Heather’s insightful discussion of De Canas v. Bica testifies to the unpredictable willfulness and shifting politics of judicial decision-making.)

I don’t see how it could be credibly disputed that federal immigration enforcement is the result of a judicially led power-grab. Have a look, for example, at this paper on federal immigration regulation from the (sympathetic) University of Minnesota’s “Human Rights Library.” In the course of trying to overwhelm the reader with the purported plethora of sources of federal power in this area, the authors unintentionally undermine their case. They are forced to concede that ”in the early immigration cases the Supreme Court faced the problem of identifying the source of the federal government’s exclusive and plenary power over immigration.” Well, yeah, it’s not easy to identify something that isn’t there.

So what happened? What usually happens: the Supreme Court began rationalizing — umm, maybe we can find it in the naturalization power; or the power to regulate foreign commerce; or the power to conduct foreign affairs; or the war power; or the power to maintain armies and navies; or the power to punish piracy and crimes on the high seas; or to impose import duties; or to codify offenses against the law of nations; or to appoint foreign diplomats; or the Migration and Imporation Caluse (art. I, sec. 9, cl. 1). If none of that sounds too compelling, there’s always the “necessary and proper clause” — a convenient catch-all: When a court can’t directly justify federal action by some enumeration of authority, it contends the action is derivatively justified as necessary to the exercise of some purportedly related enumerated power (often without a very convincing explanation of why power A not only implies power B but that the states understood this and thus clearly delegated power B).

Over time (in this case, over more than a century), this dizzying exercise devolves into judicial ipse dixit. So it was, the UMinn authors conclude, that in 1899 the Supreme Court, in the so-called Chinese Exclusion Case (Chae Chan Ping v. U.S.), “eventually found the source of the federal power to regulate immigration in a combination of international and constitutional legal principles.” The concept of national sovereignty suddenly made the federal government preeminent — and never you mind that (a) in our system, the states are also sovereign, (b) the states had been regulating immigration since the Constitution’s adoption, and (c) most things that are clear, “absolute and unqualified” don’t take 110 years to discover.

Which is to say, this was a fabrication — and one, it’s worth pointing out, that Arizona did not challenge. In the case before Judge Bolton, the state did not contest federal supremacy over immigration enforcement within Arizona’s borders. That calls into question whether the issue would properly be before the Supreme Court if the state fails to raise it as the litigation goes forward. (In my mind, it’s strictly a legal question that doesn’t require development of a factual record, so the state should be permitted to raise it in the Ninth Circuit.) Heather is quite right that where the courts will come out on preemption is an unknown. After all, those same courts, having started with a situation in which state enforcement was a given and federal enforcement was questionable, have willed us to our current straits, where we are to believe that the opposite is true.

But that’s not the way it should be. In 1837, the Supreme Court (in New York v. Miln) upheld a state law that allowed New York City to expel arriving aliens it “deemed” likely to become a public burden. As Justice Philip Barbour explained, the state had acted

to prevent her citizens from being oppressed by the support of multitudes of poor persons who come from foreign countries without possessing the means of supporting themselves. There can be no mode in which the power to regulate internal police could be more appropriately exercised. New York, from her particular situation, is perhaps more than any other city in the Union exposed to the evil of thousands of foreign emigrants arriving there, and the consequent danger of her citizens being subjected to a heavy charge in the maintenance of those who are poor. It is the duty of the state to protect its citizens from this evil; they have endeavored to do so by passing, amongst other things, the section of the law in question. We should upon principle, say that it had a right to do so. [Emphasis added.]

There is no good reason why what was true in 1837 should not be true today. Even if we accept, for argument’s sake, that the courts have discovered and justified federal powers to enact and enforce immigration laws, there is no reason that should vitiate concurrent, sovereign state authority — authority that existed before the putative federal authority, that the states have never delegated (and therefore retain), and that, in the Arizona instance, is actually consistent with pertinent federal law.

A couple of final points. Heather assumes there is a “federal interest in speaking with a single, national voice when it comes to immigration matters.” As a matter of law, if there is such an interest, I’d argue that this is a recent development in our jurisprudence. As a matter of fact, I’d contend that there may be a federal interest (i.e., the interest of the federal government, which wants to control the area) but there is no national interest. The country is divided on immigration, as we are divided on many things, and that’s fine as long as every state is not burdened by the choice of individual states not to enforce the law.

While Heather is troubled by the prospect of different states having different prosecutorial regimes for immigration, that is the way it is on many issues (drugs, guns, etc.) and it is the way it has always been on immigration. As related in the Baldacchino paper I cite above, in the so-called Passenger Cases (1849), the Court discussed the distinction between the naturalization power, which is federal, and immigration enforcement, which was a state matter. Chief Justice Roger Taney (in a dissenting opinion) argued that it was obvious that the naturalization power had been delegated to the feds because otherwise, under the privileges and immunities clause, a single state could determine for every state “what foreigner should become one of its citizens, and be entitled to hold lands, and to vote at its elections.” The court clearly assumed that different states would continue to enforce different enforcement standards.

Finally, the Supreme Court has recently been deferential to the power of states to enact and enforce law in the face of a claim that this power was trumped by the president’s capacious authority to conduct foreign affairs.

In Medellin v. Texas (2008), President Bush attempted to force Texas to vacate a Mexican national’s capital murder conviction because the state had failed to comply with the Vienna Convention obligation to allow the defendant to contact his consulate — even though the defendant had failed to make a timely Vienna Convention claim under state law. The Supreme Court held that the state’s power to enforce its valid laws was not overcome by the president’s foreign-affairs authority or his power to take care that the laws be faithfully executed. Congress had not enacted any statute that contravened state law, and the justices were not persuaded by claims that the state law frustrated the president’s ability to enforce a uniform national standard in an arena — foreign policy — where presidential power is immense.

There is a colorable argument that our jurisprudence has created a federal immigration-enforcement role that the Constitution did not make entirely clear. There should not be a credible argument that the states are precluded from enacting immigration laws that are consistent with congressional statutes.

The Corner

http://www.nationalreview.com/corner/242219/preemption-and-prosecutorial-discretion-response-andy-mccarthy-heather-mac-donald

Preemption and Prosecutorial Discretion: A Response to Andy McCarthy

Posted on August 02, 2010 9:00 AM

I am delighted that Andy McCarthy has responded to my uncertainty about Arizona’s S.B. 1070; I could not hope for a more knowledgeable and eloquent interlocutor, one whose command of legal matters is without peer.

I had wondered whether S.B. 1070 could in fact pose a constitutional problem in the following situation: Arizona law-enforcement officials inquire with ICE whether someone they have stopped is in the country illegally. ICE answers in the affirmative, but tells the Arizona officials that it is not interested in prosecuting or deporting that particular alien — in essence, telling Arizona to let him go. Nevertheless, Arizona fines or incarcerates the illegal alien for violating the new state-law version of the federal alien-registration law (which requires aliens to carry their immigration papers). In such a case, I speculated, perhaps Arizona’s decision to penalize the alien conflicts with, and is thus preempted by, federal authority over immigration matters.

Andy vigorously responded that preemption doctrine applies to Congressional laws, not to the executive enforcement of those laws. Since nothing in the federal statutory scheme regarding immigration conflicts with S.B. 1070 — or with Arizona’s decision to enforce S.B. 1070’s alien-registration section — such enforcement on Arizona’s part is not preempted by federal law.

If I am reading Andy correctly, he seems to draw a bright line between a law and its execution; I am not sure that I agree. Law has no existence without the myriad decisions necessary to its enforcement; a law and its enforcement are two sides of the same coin. The president is charged with the constitutional duty of taking “care that the laws be faithfully executed,” but inherent in that duty, as Andy readily notes, is an inevitable dose of prosecutorial discretion. Such prosecutorial discretion is present in nearly all law enforcement, to the frequent chagrin of affected parties. A police officer may simply pour out the Colt 45 that a rowdy loiterer is drinking, even though local residents would prefer that the loiterer be arrested and prosecuted for an open-container violation. The cops in turn fume when district attorneys ignore the good arrests that they have brought in for car break-ins, drug-dealing, or aggressive panhandling. But the cop who chooses not to arrest and the DA who chooses not to prosecute are as much a part of the law as the legislators who passed the criminal statutes they work under.

Congress did not mandate that every last illegal alien be deported; it set the conditions for legal entry into the country and the penalties for violating those conditions. Congress left it to the discretion of the president how he would marshal his finite resources in executing the various goals of the immigration system. In so exercising his discretion, a president has not entered into some extra-constitutional “political” territory, as Andy seems to suggest; he is operating within his constitutional legal powers. Likewise, members of Arizona’s executive branch will have discretion in enforcing S.B. 1070; they are not taking the law into some distinct political realm in so doing, but are making the law a reality.

As Andy might frame the question: Does the preemption doctrine cover executive prosecutorial discretion and other policy decisions, or just the plain language of statutes?

Outside the immigration field, there are judicial rulings that treat executive discretion in enforcing the law — what Andy refers to as “politics,” if I am reading him accurately — as included within the supremacy clause. Crosby v. National Foreign Trade Council, 630 U.S. 363 (2000), struck down a Massachusetts boycott of companies that trade with Burma. The Court held that the state boycott conflicted with the president’s discretion over congressional economic sanctions against Burma, and that the president should speak unilaterally for the country in this foreign-policy matter. Buckman v. Plaintiffs’ Legal Committee, 531 U.S. 341 (2001), held that a state tort case against a medical-device manufacturer was preempted by the FDA’s authority over medical-device approvals. The injured plaintiffs had argued that the defendant manufacturer had used fraud against the FDA to obtain approval for its device; the Court ruled that only the FDA could bring such fraud claims against manufacturers. The FDA needed to preserve its discretion over which claims to pursue, said the Court; allowing private plaintiffs to bring fraud cases could overtax its resources. Both cases can be distinguished from the immigration issue and from S.B. 1070, of course. Nevertheless, Crosby and Buckman have at least some bearing on whether executive discretionary policy falls within the ambit of preemption doctrine.

Applied to the immigration field, the question becomes: If the president decides not to enforce the immigration laws against this particular illegal alien or even against most illegal aliens, are the states free to prosecute those same aliens under a bootstrap state version of federal law? The answer to me is not obvious. The prospect of 50 different prosecutorial regimes for immigration violations is not unproblematic. As much as I believe that immigration law should be enforced much more vigorously than it currently is, such a piecemeal system of state-level immigration regimes could arguably conflict with the federal interest in speaking with a single, national voice when it comes to immigration matters.

To be sure, there is case law aplenty acknowledging that the states do have authority to regulate and criminalize matters that bear on immigration.

De Canas v. Bica, 424 U.S. 351 (1976), upheld California’s labor code banning the knowing employment of illegal aliens when such employment hurts lawful resident workers. (Justice Brennan’s opinion stands as a reminder of a lost world, when liberals cared more for the rights of workers than for multiculturalism: “Employment of illegal aliens in times of high unemployment,” he wrote for a unanimous court, “deprives citizens and legally admitted aliens of jobs; acceptance by illegal aliens of jobs on substandard terms as to wages and working conditions can seriously depress wage scales and working conditions of citizens and legally admitted aliens; and employment of illegal aliens under such conditions can diminish the effectiveness of labor unions. These local problems are particularly acute in California in light of the significant influx into that State of illegal aliens from neighboring Mexico.” You couldn’t find a labor-union president today who would utter such verboten ideas.)

But Justice Brennan stressed that California’s labor code was an exercise of the state’s police power over employment relations within the state; it was not a “regulation of immigration, which is essentially a determination of who should or should not be admitted into the country, and the conditions under which a legal entrant may remain.” (The “conditions under which a legal entrant” — much less an illegal one — “may remain” conceivably extend to enforcement policy.) Unlike other state statutes regarding alien registration and sedition, which the Court had found were preempted by federal immigration policy, in the present case, wrote Justice Brennan, “there is no indication that Congress intended to preclude state law in the area of employment regulation.”

S.B. 1070’s section 3 (which adopts and criminalizes the federal registration scheme), however, and its enforcement lie squarely within the central core of immigration law: determining who is in the country legally and how to respond to immigration violations.

Thus far am I on the fence regarding S.B. 1070’s section 3. When I read the Justice Department’s brief, however, I fall back into Arizona’s camp, so mealy-mouthed and deceptive is its argumentation. The “competing [immigration] objectives” that DOJ lists as disrupted by S.B. 1070 do not in the main conflict with S.B. 1070 at all. Those interests include, according to the Justice Department: “facilitating trade and commerce; welcoming those foreign nationals who visit or immigrate lawfully and ensuring their fair and equitable treatment wherever they may reside; responding to humanitarian concerns at the global and individual levels; and otherwise ensuring that the treatment of aliens present in our nation does not harm our foreign relations with the countries from which they come or jeopardize the treatment of U.S. citizens abroad.”

Obviously, S.B. 1070 does not interfere with trade and commerce nor with welcoming legal immigrants and visitors. I would hope that it would not conflict with a “humanitarian” dispensation for an illegal alien, but if such humanitarian relief is discretionary on the part of the executive, I’m not sure where Andy would come out on the question. If ICE said: “Hands off that illegal: he’s cooperating with us against a drug kingpin,” or, “Our feminist agenda dictates that we want to protect this allegedly battered woman against her brutish machismo partner back in Mexico,” and Arizona responds: “Tough, we’re locking these folks up anyway; what part of ‘illegal’ don’t you understand?” I’m not sure where Andy would come out.

The Justice Department is correct that S.B. 1070 has had foreign-relations repercussions. Mexico has thrown a fit in regards to S.B. 1070. So what else is new? Every concerted effort to enforce our immigration laws produces a hysterical reaction among Mexican officials, who regard unimpeded entry into the U.S. by Mexican citizens as close to a birthright (even though those same officials periodically pay lip service to the patent legitimacy of our immigration regime). As Arizona’s brief in the S.B. 1070 lawsuit points out, the Obama administration’s immediate, unqualified, and wholly inaccurate smearing of S.B. 1070 as a violation of human rights hardly contributed to a fair reception of the law in international circles. Nevertheless, as nauseating and hypocritical as Mexico’s reaction to S.B. 1070 is, it is indisputable that Arizona’s action has affected international relations, which are an executive branch responsibility. “So what?” one may well answer; “it has done so through 100 percent legitimate means.” A fair point; I’m undecided on this matter. We certainly don’t want to be held hostage to Mexico’s tantrums.

Here are two other questions that I am not certain about: Does it matter why the executive branch is not enforcing the law, and how much of a burden should it meet in justifying its non-enforcement? The closest the Obama administration’s legal papers come to acknowledging its wholesale amnesty for most illegal aliens is the coy statement: “In exercising its significant enforcement discretion, the federal government prioritizes for arrest, detention, prosecution, and removal those aliens who pose a danger to national security or a risk to public safety.” Unspoken corollary: Everyone else gets a free pass. Now what if the reason for such “prioritization” is simply resource constraints? “We’d like to go after everyone,” the federal government might say, “but we just don’t have the manpower to do so.” In that case, it might welcome S.B. 1070. “We don’t have the capacity to process this or that garden-variety illegal, but if you, Arizona, want to stick him in your local jail for his lack of papers, be my guest.” But what if the administration’s non-enforcement policy results from an affirmative preference for not enforcing the law against most illegals — should that affect the legitimacy of Arizona’s decision to undertake a more vigorous enforcement regime?

Of course, the Obama administration assiduously avoids acknowledging its blanket non-enforcement policy; the highly specific individual examples it provides of illegals whom it might choose to exempt from the law have no bearing on the administration’s industrial-strength, undiscriminating de facto amnesty.

So the administration’s lack of honesty with regards to its actual immigration policy does not earn it any points. Still, despite its bad faith, and despite Andy’s forceful and well-reasoned argument for why executive policy should enjoy no constitutional protection, I don’t think that this is a cut-and-dried matter.

Comments are closed.